alloneword wrote:chlamor wrote:If you have a list of acceptable links that can be used to support Marxist analysis please present that. Your not so cleverly disguised insults aside it seems you have little desire to reach back to a historical sense of how money came to be money and what it represents.
Au contraire, my friend. 'What it [money] represents' - and the analysis of such which Marx failed to perform is the point of my writing. By failing to adequately understand the true nature of 'money', with it's inherent, systemic and structural deficiencies, Marx bases his entire analysis on no real foundations.chlamor wrote:Your reformist perspective takes us not so far from where we are.
Since my (Gesell's) analysis examines the nature of 'money' at a deeper level than Marx (who just takes it as read that 'it is what it is', without further critical examination), how on earth can you suggest that this approach is 'reformist'? It is fundamentally more 'revolutionary', in the true sense of the word, than that of Marx. Marx is the 'reformist', merely tinkering with the controls of the machine, the inner workings of which he fails to understand.chlamor wrote:It seems that what are dealing with here is a form of sophistic argument on the web and here the web helps you in that you can ignore the very basic foundation of the argument that has been introduced in the hopes that the short half-life of individual debating points on the internet can get you back on solid ground.
Perhaps you could elucidate as to the nature of this 'very basic foundation'? Thus far I remain somewhat unconvinced that the 'foundation' of Marxist analysis lies deeper than that of Gesell.chlamor wrote:So, you repeat your previous points with disdain, hoping that what was written will go away.
I repeat my points in the vain hope that they will sink in, hoping that what will be written will either answer the points, directing me to some of Marx's words which deal with the fundamental nature of money, or graciously concede that he never actually did so.chlamor wrote:You repeat the saw about Marx without concern that you have yet to make it clear what exactly you want to have Marx say or "explain" (then you will admit he is wrong).
I'm stuggling to find a way to make it any clearer. I'll try again: What has Marx to say on the fundamental nature of 'money'? - that is, what it 'is' rather than what it does. We know what it 'does'. That is governed by it's innate nature - it cannot do otherwise.chlamor wrote:You also repeat the contention about the "magic" of money but now with a side trip on the durability of the money commodity (gold and silver also "rots", but unless we are taking yet another side trip into the "natural" money-ness of rotten gold and silver, this leads us nowhere).
Gold and silver 'rot'? News to me, I must concede. Whatever, unless you are suggesting that your own money is some hitherto unknown form of gold which rots - as opposed to 'figures on a balance sheet' which obviously doesn't, no matter how you look at it, 'money' possesses a *magical* quality (that of non-perishability) in relation to the goods it is supposed to represent. To argue otherwise is absurd.chlamor wrote:In all of this, you see the complexity of the modern forms, not as smoke obscuring your vision, but as your friend: "what about this and what about that?"
The 'complexity of the modern forms' are but the inevitable result of the innate, fundamental nature of 'money'. No 'friends' of mine, Sir!chlamor wrote:A cogent analysis lies on a different tack. Instead of looking backward with all of the issues of the modern day befuddling us, we can go back and derived money looking forward (i.e. historically).
Which surely is precisely what Gesell does and Marx fails to do.chlamor wrote: In truth, there are only two places that you correspondent can legitimately go:
Either you can argue that my short summary of the origins of money is incorrect,
or...
you can point to that point in history when the nature of money as we have outlined it, changes into something entirely different (with documentary material, please).
With regard to 'option 1', I argue that your 'short summary of the origins of money' is incomplete, inadequate and superficial. It does not comprehend the nature of money, nor it's fundamental *magical* difference (resistence to atrophy) from the goods which it is supposed to represent.
With regard to 'option 2', I have already done so above - with 'documentary material', no less.Yes - we are way past Marx - we always were, for the reason that Marx does not say 'What money is'. If he had attempted to enquire into it's nature, I could read his description and offer an opinion as to it's validity. He did not, so I cannot. All I can do is point to what Gesell and others said of 'What money is'. Your own failure to comprehend 'what money is' or offer a counter argument does not make those who can 'sophists'.chlamor wrote:We are way past Marx by this point. "Here is what money is", and the only possible response that does not tread on sophistry is to say, "that is not what it is".
At this point, nothing else matters... Not Marx, not Gesell, and not what you "think".chlamor wrote:Did you know that Anarchis was once asked what the Greeks used money for? "For figuring", he said.
There is another related discussion to this one. It is that of where such ideas come from, and the subject matter is by no means simply confined to "money". Many of the early socialists point to one or another category of political economy and say, "There is your problem". Robert Owen's "labor money" no less than Prudhoun's "interest", is an example of this.
You - erm... wouldn't be trying to sidetrack the discussion, would you? Gesell points to the fundamental nature of money and says "There is your problem". He says that unless we address the fundamental systemic problems with the nature of money (sic), we're not going to get anywhere. He then proposes real world, workable solutions ('stamp scrip' - or 'money that rusts') which when put into practice (see my post above) yield startlingly positive results, thus proving the validity of his position. The practice of these solutions then gets stamped (excuse the pun) out by the beneficiaries of the existing system, to the point where (for instance) support for such ideas is criminalised in post WWII Russia.chlamor wrote:The entire purpose of your post is to say "Marx was wrong". Nothing else is meaningful. You are simply trying to derail the original post (and to repeat the mantra). You don't want to talk about "Nature and Capital" and, this is not because you want to talk about "Nature and Money" instead.
'The entire purpose of my post' is to highlight the fundamental deficiencies in Marxist analysis of economics.
By failing to understand the root, fundamental systemic problem with what we call money, Marx and his followers would doom us to remain within a system which is inherently flawed. The fact that 'money' has the *magical* properties which differentiate it from the goods that it is supposed to represent, it matters not what one does with it nor how one seeks to control it. It is a system, a machine which can only and will only ever yield one inevitable result, regardless of the political will or affiliations of those whose lives it permeates.
The present system, with it's *magic* money, enables two things: Hoarding, which artificially restricts the supply of money, rendering it a powerful political tool, rather than the 'neutral medium of exchange' that Marx supposed, and Usury, the bastard child, whereby those restricting the supply may 'profit' from it. So embedded has the practice become, that the actual creation of money is via usury - money is 'borrowed' into existence which yields interest. Logically, since the only money that exists is that which is 'created' in this manner, there can never be enough in existence to pay off the principle debt plus the interest.
This fact creates a system that's very existance is predicated upon 'growth', where anything that is merely 'sustainable' has by definition 'failed'. The inevitable consequences of this mechanism upon this planet and it's population are all to apparent. Is that not what your original post was about?
Here's some solid ground:
The circulation of commodities is the starting-point of capital. The production of commodities, their circulation, and that more developed form of their circulation called commerce, these form the historical ground-work from which it rises. The modern history of capital dates from the creation in the 16th century of a world-embracing commerce and a world-embracing market.
If we abstract from the material substance of the circulation of commodities, that is, from the exchange of the various use-values, and consider only the economic forms produced by this process of circulation, we find its final result to be money: this final product of the circulation of commodities is the first form in which capital appears.
As a matter of history, capital, as opposed to landed property, invariably takes the form at first of money; it appears as moneyed wealth, as the capital of the merchant and of the usurer. [1] But we have no need to refer to the origin of capital in order to discover that the first form of appearance of capital is money. We can see it daily under our very eyes. All new capital, to commence with, comes on the stage, that is, on the market, whether of commodities, labour, or money, even in our days, in the shape of money that by a definite process has to be transformed into capital.
The first distinction we notice between money that is money only, and money that is capital, is nothing more than a difference in their form of circulation.
The simplest form of the circulation of commodities is C-M-C, the transformation of commodities into money, and the change of the money back again into commodities; or selling in order to buy. But alongside of this form we find another specifically different form: M-C-M, the transformation of money into commodities, and the change of commodities back again into money; or buying in order to sell. Money that circulates in the latter manner is thereby transformed into, becomes capital, and is already potentially capital.
Now let us examine the circuit M-C-M a little closer. It consists, like the other, of two antithetical phases. In the first phase, M-C, or the purchase, the money is changed into a commodity. In the second phase, C-M, or the sale, the commodity is changed back again into money. The combination of these two phases constitutes the single movement whereby money is exchanged for a commodity, and the same commodity is again exchanged for money; whereby a commodity is bought in order to be sold, or, neglecting the distinction in form between buying and selling, whereby a commodity is bought with money, and then money is bought with a commodity. [2] The result, in which the phases of the process vanish, is the exchange of money for money, M-M. If I purchase 2,000 lbs. of cotton for £100, and resell the 2,000 lbs. of cotton for £110, I have, in fact, exchanged £100 for £110, money for money.
Now it is evident that the circuit M-C-M would be absurd and without meaning if the intention were to exchange by this means two equal sums of money, £100 for £100. The miser’s plan would be far simpler and surer; he sticks to his £100 instead of exposing it to the dangers of circulation. And yet, whether the merchant who has paid £100 for his cotton sells it for £110, or lets it go for £100, or even £50, his money has, at all events, gone through a characteristic and original movement, quite different in kind from that which it goes through in the hands of the peasant who sells corn, and with the money thus set free buys clothes. We have therefore to examine first the distinguishing characteristics of the forms of the circuits M-C-M and C-M-C, and in doing this the real difference that underlies the mere difference of form will reveal itself.
Let us see, in the first place, what the two forms have in common.
Both circuits are resolvable into the same two antithetical phases, C-M, a sale, and M-C, a purchase. In each of these phases the same material elements - a commodity, and money, and the same economic dramatis personae, a buyer and a seller - confront one another. Each circuit is the unity of the same two antithetical phases, and in each case this unity is brought about by the intervention of three contracting parties, of whom one only sells, another only buys, while the third both buys and sells.
What, however, first and foremost distinguishes the circuit C-M-C from the circuit M-C-M, is the inverted order of succession of the two phases. The simple circulation of commodities begins with a sale and ends with a purchase, while the circulation of money as capital begins with a purchase and ends with a sale. In the one case both the starting-point and the goal are commodities, in the other they are money. In the first form the movement is brought about by the intervention of money, in the second by that of a commodity.
In the circulation C-M-C, the money is in the end converted into a commodity, that serves as a use-value; it is spent once for all. In the inverted form, M-C-M, on the contrary, the buyer lays out money in order that, as a seller, he may recover money. By the purchase of his commodity he throws money into circulation, in order to withdraw it again by the sale of the same commodity. He lets the money go, but only with the sly intention of getting it back again. The money, therefore, is not spent, it is merely advanced. [3]
In the circuit C-M-C, the same piece of money changes its place twice. The seller gets it from the buyer and pays it away to another seller. The complete circulation, which begins with the receipt, concludes with the payment, of money for commodities. It is the very contrary in the circuit M-C-M. Here it is not the piece of money that changes its place twice, but the commodity. The buyer takes it from the hands of the seller and passes it into the hands of another buyer. Just as in the simple circulation of commodities the double change of place of the same piece of money effects its passage from one hand into another, so here the double change of place of the same commodity brings about the reflux of the money to its point of departure.
Such reflux is not dependent on the commodity being sold for more than was paid for it. This circumstance influences only the amount of the money that comes back. The reflux itself takes place, so soon as the purchased commodity is resold, in other words, so soon as the circuit M-C-M is completed. We have here, therefore, a palpable difference between the circulation of money as capital, and its circulation as mere money.
The circuit C-M-C comes completely to an end, so soon as the money brought in by the sale of one commodity is abstracted again by the purchase of another.
If, nevertheless, there follows a reflux of money to its starting-point, this can only happen through a renewal or repetition of the operation. If I sell a quarter of corn for £3, and with this £3 buy clothes, the money, so far as I am concerned, is spent and done with. It belongs to the clothes merchant. If I now sell a second quarter of corn, money indeed flows back to me, not however as a sequel to the first transaction, but in consequence of its repetition. The money again leaves me, so soon as I complete this second transaction by a fresh purchase. Therefore, in the circuit C-M-C, the expenditure of money has nothing to do with its reflux. On the other hand, in M-C-M, the reflux of the money is conditioned by the very mode of its expenditure. Without this reflux, the operation fails, or the process is interrupted and incomplete, owing to the absence of its complementary and final phase, the sale.
The circuit C-M-C starts with one commodity, and finishes with another, which falls out of circulation and into consumption. Consumption, the satisfaction of wants, in one word, use-value, is its end and aim. The circuit M-C-M, on the contrary, commences with money and ends with money. Its leading motive, and the goal that attracts it, is therefore mere exchange-value.
In the simple circulation of commodities, the two extremes of the circuit have the same economic form. They are both commodities, and commodities of equal value. But they are also use-values differing in their qualities, as, for example, corn and clothes. The exchange of products, of the different materials in which the labour of society is embodied, forms here the basis of the movement. It is otherwise in the circulation M-C-M, which at first sight appears purposeless, because tautological. Both extremes have the same economic form. They are both money, and therefore are not qualitatively different use-values; for money is but the converted form of commodities, in which their particular use-values vanish. To exchange £100 for cotton, and then this same cotton again for £100, is merely a roundabout way of exchanging money for money, the same for the same, and appears to be an operation just as purposeless as it is absurd. [4] One sum of money is distinguishable from another only by its amount. The character and tendency of the process M-C-M, is therefore not due to any qualitative difference between its extremes, both being money, but solely to their quantitative difference. More money is withdrawn from circulation at the finish than was thrown into it at the start. The cotton that was bought for £100 is perhaps resold for £100 + £10 or £110. The exact form of this process is therefore M-C-M', where M' = M + D M = the original sum advanced, plus an increment. This increment or excess over the original value I call “surplus-value.” The value originally advanced, therefore, not only remains intact while in circulation, but adds to itself a surplus-value or expands itself. It is this movement that converts it into capital.
http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/wo ... 1/ch04.htm